Essay about CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: PROOF IS SIMPLY BEYOND THE CAPACITY

CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: PROOF IS SIMPLY BEYOND THE CAPACITY

Certain individuals who commit crimes do so at their own free will, and many have no qualms as to the consequences of their actions. To some, it matters not the possibil­ity that if they are caught, there is the chance they may be executed. Sometimes the crimes committed by certain per­sons are done so in a manner that would bewilder any other human being.

My personal belief is that there is no need for capital punishment in our society. Advocates say that capital punish­ment is needed in order to deter future criminals, but this is not entirely the case. Research has shown that capital punish­ment, as a deterrent, has no positive or negative effect. An influential student of the deterrence question, Thorsten Sellin, conducted a study that would attempt to determine the effect of capital punishment on future crime. He studied the homi­cide rates in contiguous states, some with and some without the death penalty, on the assumption that these states were as alike as possible in character of population, social and eco­nomic conditions, etc. His conclusion was that the death pen­alty had no effect on the murder rate (Sellin, 63).

This is not to say that the study performed by Sellin was perfect, for it did contain flaws. In his attempt, he looked for correlations between the homicide rate and the legal status of the death penalty, rather than the number of executions actu­ally carried out in the states where it was legal punishment. As it may be true that contiguous states are similar in certain respects, their differences may be quite apparent. Sellin looked for characteristics evident in all of the states he compared, but these same factors may not be part of the real reason that leads to homicide. He had no way of knowing if these states were equal in all other respects, such as apprehending and convicting those who commit murder. There is simply no absolute in controlling all factors.

The issue of deterrence has been the basis on which ad­vocates or abolitionists have grounded their arguments. It would be safe to assume that both sides have varying defini­tions for the term “deterrence” and the manner in which they utilize that definition to their advantage. Gertrude Ezorsky offers a dichotomous definition of deterrence that is useful in deciphering the meanings behind the arguments.

Ezorsky makes a distinction between the effects of a threat of a punishment and the effects of the actual punishment. The threat of punishment is directed to all members of society. It is grounded in the criminal law and is enforced by members of the police, prosecution attorneys, courts, and pris­ons. There must be a connection between the law and the system of justice for they are to be any sort of control in soci­ety. As long as the threat of punishment has a restraining ef­fect in regards to criminal conduct, this is called general de­terrence.

Ezorsky makes three points in her definition of general deterrence. Her first point is the need to take into account the danger of generalization. Distinction must be carefully made in the different types of offenses because they vary in motiva­tion. Any discussion of general deterrence must be in the con­texts of norms and an analysis of the deviations from those norms. The second point of her definition is that people react differently. She divides the population into three distinct groups: (1) the good, law-abiding citizens who do not require the threat of law to live by the rules set by society; (2) the criminal group—those who fear the law, but not to the extent that they do not break the law; and (3) the potential criminals who would have broken the law had it not been for the threat of punishment.

I find two problems with this categorization. The first is the ability to decipher, which individuals fall into which cat­egory. Granted, there will be those who are easily catego­rized, but those who are not—how, and where, do we draw the line? What sort of criteria should be set to pinpoint one individual from another? The second problem is that we are not answering the problem of how to punish those who break the law; rather, we are simply further subdividing the guilty from the innocent. While this may benefit those who have already committed a crime, how will it affect those who are contemplating a life of crime? More importantly, how will we ever really know who is capable of committing a crime?

The third point offered by Ezorsky is what is called the moral or educative effect of the criminal la\v. She further states that punishment is not only the artificial creation of a risk of unpleasant consequences, but also a means of expressing so­cial disapproval. Again, I see another potential problem in her analysis. Those individuals, who commit crimes, many times, care not about what society thinks of them. They do what they do because of social environments, insanity, and other reasons that we do not know about. Those who do care what society thinks of them would have been rehabilitated in the penal system anyway.

The second aspect of this dichotomy is called special deterrence. This occurs when an individual who has already been punished is still under the threat of the law, yet the mo­tivation for future activities is more complex than before. The difference is that the person knows what it is like to be pros­ecuted and punished. The threat of punishment has vanished because, if individuals are to commit future crimes, they were not deterred in their actions; the law was not able to confirm the individual. Deterrence is in the presence of the actual ex­perience of punishment.

Special deterrence refers to actual punishment and is usually discussed in terms of reform and rehabilitation. Prima facie, it seems natural for the experience of punishment to strengthen fear. Again, the effect of punishment depends on the individual. First-time offenders are probably going to re­gret the crime they committed from the very moment they are caught. (Another question to ask is whether people would feel guilty if they were never caught.) Now, professional crimi­nals will try to talk their way out of the incident until they realize that is useless and accept the notion they will be pun­ished.

The above description highlights the theory that fear bears, at least in some form, influence on individuals who commit a crime. They realize that they have committed a shameful act, and the incident acts as a moral revelation. Most criminals, before arrest, do not think of themselves as crimi­nals, but that notion of breaking the law finally hits home when they are caught. Even if they are not prosecuted or given any form of punishment, they will feel shameful because of the aspect of detection.

Another view of capital punishment is offered by Jerry Cederblom. He acknowledges the two main theories advanced by contemporary debaters of capital punishment: the first being utilitarianism, where punishment is justified by appeal to consequences such as deterrence; and the second, retributivism, which has traditionally appealed to the notion of “just desserts.” He believes both of these theories are flawed and attempts to provide a compromise, which he calls the Retributive Liability Theory of Punishment. The theory pre­sented by Cederblom contends that it is preferable (on re­tributive grounds) that harm fall on the guilty. Utilitarians view deterrence simply as a future benefit of punishment; this theory deploys deterrence as a retributive rationale for pun­ishment.

The Retributive Liability Theory (RLT) can be summa­rized as follows. A person should be punished for an offense only: (1) if the person committed the offense, or (2) if offenses of this kind go unpunished, then more offenses would occur. The punishment should be no more harmful than the intended acts of the individual. The rationale is that the individual has created a situation, which dictates that if the individual is not harmed (by being punished), and then harm will fall on some innocent victim (in society).

Considering that RLT does not base punishment on “just desserts,” how can it be a retributive theory?

The answer is that according to RLT it is guilt that justi­fies punishing an offender, and the predictable harm of an offender’s intended act limits the amount of punishment the offender should receive, even though circumstances can al­low the amount of punishment within this limit to vary (Cederblom, 307).

In essence, the reasoning behind RLT is in its objective, which is to distribute harm toward the guilty rather than to­ward the innocent.

In recognizing the advantages of RLT over its rivals, it is also necessary to point out the flaws in this theory. The first problem is that RLT claims that the punishment should be no greater than the intended acts of the offender. How can harm to a victim be measured? Cederblom attempts to compensate for this problem. He states, “A punishment is excessive if the offender would reasonably prefer to suffer the probable con­sequences of the offense . . . rather than suffer the probable consequences of the punishment” (Ibid, 313).

The second problem is the extent to which punishment actually deters crime. It should also be emphasized that in no way does RLT assert or depend on the proposition that pun­ishment deters crime. Evidence obtained to determine the ef­fectiveness of punishment in deterring crime is unreliable.

Thirdly, how well does RLT answer the question of “Why punish?” We maintain that if an individual commits wrong against another, or to society as a whole, then it is morally preferable to punish that individual. Retributive liability al­lows the same autonomy as retributivism (our own voluntary acts determine what harm can be inflicted on us), but harm is inflicted only if the result is savings in harm to victims.

It is evident that the issue of capital punishment is com­plex and intricate in its understanding and comprehension. The future of this form of punishment is unclear because the evidence in favor of it, and against it, is interpreted in differ­ent ways that allow proponents or opponents to advance their own views. What also hinders the advance of this debate is that fact that the installation and implementation of capital punishment is inconsistent, for it is abolished, then brought back again. Many factors are taken into account in determin­ing whether capital punishment is effective, but I am in com­plete agreement with Peter Passell when he says, “proof is simply beyond the capacity of empirical social science” (Passell, 79).